logo
The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and ‘Activism'

The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and ‘Activism'

The Wire10 hours ago

Menu
हिंदी తెలుగు اردو
Home Politics Economy World Security Law Science Society Culture Editor's Pick Opinion
Support independent journalism. Donate Now
Society
The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and 'Activism'
Ajay Skaria
5 minutes ago
Spending some time on Ashoka University founder Sanjeev Bikhchandani's recent article may be helpful. First, it provides a concrete illustration of how generative AI can inhibit the capacity for critical thinking. Second, it helps us think about what we as teachers and citizens can do to guide those whose capacity for critical analysis has been weakened by AI.
'Ships in the Dark' a. 1927 painting by Paul Klee. Photo: Wikipedia.
Real journalism holds power accountable
Since 2015, The Wire has done just that.
But we can continue only with your support.
Contribute now
Last summer, while in Kerala, I happened to read Benjamín Labatut's The Maniac. I was drawn to it because, two years earlier, a very dear friend had gifted me his previous book, When We Cease to Understand the World. Like that book, The Maniac is difficult to classify. It is fiction but draws so heavily on historical events that to call it fiction seems a bit of a stretch, though it would be even more of stretch to call it anything else. So let's resort to the copout of just calling it a book.
Benjamin Labatut's 'The Maniac'.
Though one might say it focuses primarily on the life and afterlife of John von Neumann, in the process The Maniac also traces the rise of artificial intelligence. Given the themes of his previous book, I have no doubt that Labatut is acutely aware of the social, political, and ecological implications of AI, but in The Maniac he focuses principally on its intellectual aspect; I shall be doing the same here (though, as we shall see, this may not really be possible). One of the book's most compelling chapters comes toward the end, when the world champion at Go, Lee Sedol, plays against an artificial intelligence program created by Google, AlphaGo, and loses. Go is an infinitely more complicated game than chess, and the kind of brute computational power that made possible the early unbeatable programs in chess would not have succeeded here. AlphaGo's creators built it instead on the more supple form of artificial intelligence, based on 'self-play and reinforcement learning, which meant that, in essence, it had taught itself how to play.'
In The Maniac, Sedol describes his feeling after one of the moves: 'I thought AlphaGo was based on probability calculation and it was merely a machine. But when I saw this move it changed my mind. Surely AlphaGo is creative. This move made me think about Go in a new light. What does creativity mean in Go? It was not just a good, or great, or a powerful move. It was meaningful.' And then, in another game, Sedol makes a similar move, resulting in the only game he wrests from AlphaGo. Labatut writes: 'Facing each other, Lee and the computer had managed to stray beyond the limits of Go, casting a new and terrible beauty, a logic more powerful than reason that will send ripples far and wide.'
Labatut's book, and that episode in particular, came to mind as an achingly poignant counterpoint while I read the response from one of Ashoka University's founders, Sanjeev Bikhchandani, to a former student from the University who wrote to him protesting the administration's silence on the hounding and eventual arrest on sedition charges of Professor Ali Khan Mahmudabad for his very reflective Facebook post. (The Supreme Court decision that released him on bail also has some astoundingly weak reasoning.) Bikhchandani vigorously defends the university's inaction over Mahmudabad's arrest and harassment, reproducing at length in the process an answer that Google AI generated for him when he asked it the question, 'Are all liberal arts universities activist in nature?' Bikhchandani says that he agrees with the AI's answer, and goes on to buttress it (to his mind) with additional points.
I do not want to spend too much time on the specific arguments that Bikhchandani makes. The relatively valid ones are also very obvious ones: educational institutions cannot easily take strongly oppositional positions, especially against authoritarian regimes that do not follow or that systematically weaponise the rule of law; university administrations deal with regulators not only through public statements but also through institutional channels less in the public eye, and these administrations have only limited leeway in defying regulators; universities need money to function, and raising money for Ashoka is not easy. At a time when the attack on Ali Khan Mahmudabad is likely 'an excuse to corner and target Ashoka University,' I can certainly understand its administrators' and trustees' wanting to proceed cautiously.
Two matters, however, vitiate these valid arguments. For one, there is all that his letter gets wrong, or glosses over. To briefly respond: as Priya Ramani notes, Bikhchandani's recollection that the college he studied in, St. Stephens, was free of activism during his time there is quite wrong. And the contrast he seems to be venturing between academic freedom and free speech is quite muddled, as would be clear to those more familiar with the relation and distinction, laid out very nicely in an essay by Adam Sitze. Besides, even his insistence that Mahmudabad was not engaged in academic freedom since he was engaged in speech outside academic venues does not quite hold up when we remember that Ashoka University's trustees and administration failed to defend Sabyasachi Das after the publication of his scholarly article on democratic backsliding in Indian elections.
But even more worrisome is the second issue – the banality of Bikhchandani's arguments. This is a meta-issue, so to speak. The banal is worse than the wrong because the banal is also the abandonment of reflectiveness; it is the subversion of the ability to think critically about right and wrong because what is attenuated here is the ability to make meaningful distinctions about right and wrong.
Indeed, if Labatut's book is an exploration of how AI might allow us – us, humans – to reach new artistic and intellectual and critical levels, Bikhchandani's article is a perfect example of the dulling of the critical – I deliberately do not say intellectual – faculties that will affect most people who allow their analytical capacities to be controlled by AI.
Spending some more time on Bikhchandani's article may be helpful in two ways. First, it provides a concrete illustration of how generative AI can inhibit the capacity for critical thinking. Second, it helps us think about what we as teachers and citizens can do to guide those whose capacity for critical analysis has been weakened by AI.
§
Over the last three or so years, I have increasingly been incorporating into my courses a distinctive sort of assignment – one where students generate an answer using the AI involved in Large Language Models or LLMs (most stick to ChatGPT) to questions based on course material, and then produce a revised and meta-reflective version of the answer, both modifying it and explaining what they changed around and why.
My students and I have found that when these models are fed social sciences-oriented questions (for now, let's just gloss those as questions where fidelity to facts is crucial) they get too many of their facts wrong. And when they are fed humanities-oriented questions (let's gloss those as questions where issues of meaning have to be probed), they are not so much wrong as banal, tending toward pabulum. Either way, what ChatGPT usually spits out is the kind of answer that in my classes would by itself be in the C range, or at most a B minus.
In their engagement with the AI answer, differences between students also become clear. For the most reflective, the ChatGPT answer becomes an occasion to review their own presumptions more critically. What often results is something more brilliant and insightful than would likely have resulted if they had answered the question directly, without the ChatGPT detour.
But the less reflective students usually find themselves concurring with ChatGPT. Even if they add quite a few factual corrections, they find it difficult to do more than add a small caveat or two to the humanistic questions of meaning that frame ChatGPT's arguments. And the students in the low C range end up offering etiolated versions of even the ChatGPT answer. How to help these weaker students develop a more thoughtful relation with generative AI is a matter that I continue to puzzle over. One thing that I have found somewhat helpful is asking students what groupthink might be embedded in the answers, and how and why might they want to take these answers apart.
Illustration: Yutong Liu & Kingston School of Art/https://betterimagesofai.org/https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
Bikhchandani's reply to the student remains at the level of an LLM AI answer, as he himself effectively declares, and at times it sinks to the level of an etiolated version of such an answer; it is a good illustration of the kind of paper which in my undergraduate classes would get at best a C plus. In his case, of course, the problem starts with the question itself. From what I have seen, to get LLM AI models such as Google AI or ChatGPT to produce a half-decent answer to such a banal and generic question would be well-nigh impossible.
One could, of course, come up with a more interesting answer to the question, but that would have to begin by reframing the question or probing its presumptions: asking more deeply what a liberal education is, asking what is glossed over in the term 'activist,' asking whether faculty and students and administration engage with 'activism' in necessarily different ways, and so on. But at present, at least, AI like Google's is incapable of that work. (To be clear, my remarks are only about the type of LLM AI Bikhchandani used: I have myself found, and others have, too, that when fed a delimited corpus and asked to generate answers on that basis, AI can be astonishingly good, and I can perhaps be persuaded that if I spent more time with feeding generative AI the right material, I might experience an AlphaGo moment.)
Reframing Bikhchandani's question by critically parsing it would also be beginning to answer it. To carry out that task with the care it deserves would take longer than is possible in the compass of a short piece. But since Bikhchandani seems to have at least some curiosity about these matters, maybe one owes it to him to provide briefly the protocols that may help him critically move beyond the simple-minded embrace of Google AI pabulum.
§
So, in that educative spirit, here goes: No, 'liberal arts universities' are not 'necessarily activist' in nature – on this matter, Google AI is quite correct. Paradoxically, however, this is for several nested reasons which are about the different forms of action and activism at work in the concept of the university.
1) The relation between action and activism is a complex one, and we often invoke 'activism' in intellectually lazy ways. To put it very schematically for now: action that challenges what are taken to be prevalent social norms, whether of the right or left, is more likely to be classed as activism.
2) Conceptually, what distinguishes the modern university is that it is, for those who aspire to abide by its principle, a place focused on education as an autonomous end, rather than merely a place for technical training – that is, merely a means to transmit already formulated knowledge. I know, of course, that this aspiration has never been realised, and has always been undercut in many ways: from its very inception, there have been social exclusions that have shaped access to it for both faculty and students; since the 1980s, there has also been the neoliberal subordination of autonomy to the rhetoric of 'excellence.' But the aspirational dimension of the university cannot be easily extinguished, and this dimension is arguably especially important for the historically marginalised as they articulate the terms of the dignity they have been long denied. To treat education as an autonomous end means that we pursue both rational explanation and reflection as qualities in themselves. Such pursuit may lead to a departure from existing norms in a society or even within the university itself. This is why dissent is constitutive of the university as institution. And dissent even in speech means action. (Strikingly, Google AI recognises this more clearly than Bikhchandani. Its answer to him specifies that liberal arts education involves the 'development of critical thinking skills, not necessarily a commitment to activism.' Yes indeed, but this does not mean that activism is only 'a choice,' as Bikhchandani's sloppy regurgitation of Google AI's answer assumes.)
3) In other words, the modern university is founded on a distinction between thought/speech and action: the university is the place for thinking and speaking, and the world is the place for action. But that distinction is not an opposition. The terms bleed into each other: speech itself is an act, as is evident from the cases of Sabyasachi Das and Ali Khan Mahmudabad. Thought in this understanding has its meaning precisely because it is meant to inform and shape action, precisely because it assumed that action without thought is unacceptable The very commitment to action means that thinking must intervene in or at least speak up about action wherever the latter seems unthinking. Is this not activism? And should not university administrations defend this sort of 'activism' as the very principle of the university, even if on occasion, as when facing authoritarian regimes, administrations must choose their battles and defences strategically?
Illustration: Hanna Barakat & Archival Images of AI + AIxDESIGN / https://betterimagesofai.org / https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
4) So far I have addressed university education but not the adjective 'liberal.' In its application as an adjective to education, 'liberal' refers, as Wikipedia notes, to 'a system or course of education suitable for the cultivation of a free (Latin: liber) human being.' This sense of 'liberal' as an experience of being free – call it liberality – predates liberalism as an ideology which articulates a particular institutional order of freedom. And 'liberal education' has arguably retained more of that open-ended commitment to the idea of freedom, asking also what freedom is, than liberalism as ideology. It is precisely because of the destabilizing emphasis on 'free' that a liberal education tends by its very nature to be driven by a democratic spirit. But save in caricatural stoicisms, there is no such thing as a freedom of the mind that does not strive for a freedom in action. Would this not be another reason why a liberal education necessarily inclines toward not just action but activism? (This, though, is a very different matter from the claim that universities are 'necessarily activist,' as a shoddy – too quickly transitive – logic might assume.)
5) The focus here is not just on liberal education; it is on a liberal arts education. The phrase 'liberal arts' specifies a particular way of inhabiting the world – through critique. The crux of a liberal arts education as a concept is the combination of the sciences, centred as they are on explanation, expertise, and questions of 'what,' and the arts, centred as they are around reflection and questions of 'who.' Until just a few decades back, reflection was dominated by humanist reason, or a reason that made 'the human,' with all its constitutive exclusions, into the 'who.' Critical theory, increasingly prominent since the 1980s, represents an alternative tradition, one that is not humanist reason, but is not without reason. It emerges from the encounter, in friendship, of reasoning with the other and others it minoritises or places at its margins.
5) By at least the late 20th century, moreover, reflection had come include also the capacity to reflect critically on reason and try to practice a responsibility to what reason excludes – surely this could be one way of describing what is distinctive about critical theory.
6) While it makes sense empirically to distinguish between liberal universities and technical universities (those that teach only professional skills, and nothing of the humanities and social sciences), that distinction has no conceptual purchase. Even technical universities, when they treat technical education as an autonomous end, cannot avoid the liberal commitment involved in the undecidable and open-ended sense of freedom.
7) There is indeed a sense in which universities as institutions should not take activist positions, as Bikhchandani avers. But that sense becomes very complicated when we are attentive to it. The principal reason that universities might eschew activism is to keep open the institutional and conceptual space for students and faculty to engage in critical thought and the action – 'activism'? – from which thought is, in any meaningful sense, inseparable. This opening up of a space for students and faculty through institutional neutrality is an implication of the University of Chicago's Kalven report. To complicate things further, this emphasis on institutional neutrality does not always work, as critics have pointed out. For universities' own eschewal of activism remains tenuous: they must nourish in the wider societies of which they are part the capacity to engage in the critical thought that universities at their best embody. What happens when this nourishing of the capacity for critical thought is itself at odds with dominant or prevalent values in wider society? At that moment, should we say that a university pursuing its constitutive commitment to autonomous education has become activist?
I know there is more to be said about each of these points, and also that there are more points to be made. But for now, consider this as offering some provocations for lifting Bikhchandani's C-plus level Google AI/ChatGPT-type piece to the kind of analysis one would expect from somebody who has had a liberal education. I do very much hope that Bikhchandani will take this opportunity to cultivate a deeper-than-AI understanding of liberal education, and more broadly of education as an autonomous activity: it would be wonderful to have trustees and founders who have such an understanding, whether in India or in the US, where they have repeatedly failed to understand what university education is about. Luckily, if Bikhchandani decides to go this route, there are many brilliant teachers at Ashoka University, including Ali Khan Mahmudabad, who can guide him.
The gap between the AI answer to Bikhchandani's question and a more thoughtful reflection can also bring us back to what I have not been able to take up in this brief piece: the social and political dangers that AI poses. Where AI as an intellectual formation is dominant, I do not how we can avoid the dominance of the banal in social and political life. True, this banality may be most evident in the LLM type of AI, but it arguably occurs in more insidious ways in every form of AI as we know them today. And this social and political violence is quite apart from the tremendous environmental violence of AI.
§
There remains one other matter to be taken up: why have Bikhchandani's critical capacities – again, not at all to be confused with intellectual capacities – been so affected as to make him incapable of going beyond a Google AI-level understanding what a liberal arts education involves? My interest in this question does not centre on Bikhchandani individually or personally. For now at least, I am quite incurious about that. I am concerned more with the structural position he exemplifies. For Bikhchandani is not an exception. Silicon Valley and the worlds of finance, industry, and advertising teem with intelligent neoliberals who display a similar incomprehension about liberal education, who formulate banal questions about education (and many other subjects), and who do not even recognize the banality of their questions or the answers they generate.
What accounts for this pervasive Dunning-Kruger effect? Put very schematically, it seems to me that a constitutive blindness is at work. Silicon Valley, as well as worlds such as those of finance or technology, deal primarily with issues that seem best addressed by a hypothetical imperative (that is to say, addressing issues that can be resolved in an 'if X, then Y' manner). Hypothetical imperatives, exemplified in instrumental reason, do not require persuasion or conversation. By contrast, as Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak famously notes, education involves the 'uncoercive rearrangement of desires.'
I would add two observations to Spivak's remark: it is not just education, but also democratic sociality itself (including the capitalist sociality embodied in consumerism and advertising) that involves an uncoercive rearrangement of desires. Second, what is distinctive about modern education, especially at it gets involved in the question of reflection, is that here the uncoercive rearrangement of desires proceeds through critique, which is also to say through a division of the self, or a constant autocritique of desires. The act of loving another in their otherness is the other activity—the primary activity, really, of which education as an autonomous activity is but one privileged institutional form—in which the uncoercive rearrangement of desires proceeds through a division of the self. Precisely this insurmountable division of the self separates education, and love of the other in their otherness, from the uncoercive rearrangement of desires involved in consumerism, including most consumption of social media.
The current crisis in the legitimacy of 'higher education' (the sphere in which education is most often regarded as an autonomous activity), and the increasing claim that universities are overrun by 'activists,' are surely related to a transformation in the relations between these three phenomena—the hypothetical imperative, liberal education as an other-oriented uncoercive rearrangement of desires, and consumerism as a self-oriented uncoercive rearrangement of desires.
Illustration: Kathryn Conrad / https://betterimagesofai.org / https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
Until about the 1980s, it seems fair to say, the relation between the disciplines in the university and the hypothetical imperative was a cozy one. Thus, for much of the modern period, as Priya Satia notes, 'historians have not been critics but abettors of those in power'; the hypothetical imperative and liberal education seemed to condense in the same being—the one whom Frantz Fanon famously describes as 'the white man.' This was a time when it was possible to understand the hypothetical imperative as instrumental rationality, and liberal education as substantive or value rationality. This was a time when it was possible for many to hope that all would be well if only substantive rationality could control instrumental rationality, even as critics like Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno pointed to its impossibility. This was a time when it was commonplace to encounter the assertion that technology was not itself bad, and that what mattered was what 'man' did with it.
By the 80s, however, the breakdown of that cozy relation was well under way. Two developments reinforced each other. On the one hand, neoliberalism emphasised the hypothetical imperative even more aggressively and had much less patience with the celebration of value rationality. What seemed much more attractive to this new order of the hypothetical imperative were the self-oriented forms of the uncoercive rearrangement of desires. Now, even for sympathetic neoliberals, liberal education can be affirmed only to the extent that it is a private pleasure, something carried out for one's private edification. Bikhchandani exemplifies this view in some of his remarks, as, for instance, in his yearning to be able to treat Ashoka as he would a private company. As for the neoconservative populisms that are becoming increasingly powerful, they perhaps recognize more clearly than the neoliberal position that it may be difficult to contain the university in this way, given its conceptual premises; this is why they seek to destroy the university as we know it.
On the other hand, universities have seen the rise of various forms of critical theory, and the presence in much larger numbers of groups who had once been excluded from higher education. This has led to much less patience with value rationality, much more recognition of the fact that what was celebrated as value rationality was often the values of the dominant. At the same time, dissatisfaction with the world of the hypothetical imperative and its close twin, the self-oriented forms of the uncoercive rearrangement of desires, intensified. The university, and especially its students and faculty, increasingly emerged as the locus of the critique—a hesitant and often internally contradictory one, to be sure—of wider society to the extent that it was constituted by the hypothetical imperative and the self-centered uncoercive rearrangement of desires.
It is this enormous gap that makes liberal education as a concept incomprehensible to somebody like Bikhchandani. At most, as I noted, his neoliberal perspective can celebrate liberal education as a private good – never as a public one. To treat it as a public good would be to acknowledge and affirm its potential to remake society. This neoliberalism – unlike liberalism – finds difficult to do. Indeed, Bikhchandani's incomprehension of the liberal university – his perception that the university has become a locus primarily of 'activism' – is more than anything a telling symptom of the attenuation of the critical tools with which to understand liberal education, or education as an autonomous activity.
Ajay Skaria teaches in the Department of History and Institute for Global Studies at the University of Minnesota. This essay draws in part of some arguments expanded at greater length in his essay 'Gaza and the Unsettling Equality of Academic Freedom,' which is forthcoming in Critical Times (8:1).
This essay first appeared on the Critical Times ' blog ' In the Midst.'
The Wire is now on WhatsApp. Follow our channel for sharp analysis and opinions on the latest developments.
Make a contribution to Independent Journalism
Related News
Ashoka University Can't Call Its Refusal to Stand Up to BJP's Bullying 'Institutional Neutrality'
Founders of Ashoka Should Know that a University Can't be Equated With Hierarchies of a Corporate Office
Is Ashoka University the Next Target After Professor Ali Khan?
Who Gets to Think in India?
Supreme Court's Bail Condition on Ashoka Professor Mahmudabad: Has Dissent Become Disorder?
On Science and Changing Culture: A Conversation with Professor P. Balaram
Ashoka Prof Arrested For 'Endangering Sovereignty' Over Post Criticising Jingoism, Sent to Custody Till May 20
'Inverted the Meaning, Invented an Issue': Ashoka Professor on Women's Panel's Reaction to Army Post
The Curious Crusade of Renu Bhatia Against Ashoka Professor Mahmudabad
View in Desktop Mode
About Us
Contact Us
Support Us
© Copyright. All Rights Reserved.

Orange background

Try Our AI Features

Explore what Daily8 AI can do for you:

Comments

No comments yet...

Related Articles

The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and ‘Activism'
The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and ‘Activism'

The Wire

time10 hours ago

  • The Wire

The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and ‘Activism'

Menu हिंदी తెలుగు اردو Home Politics Economy World Security Law Science Society Culture Editor's Pick Opinion Support independent journalism. Donate Now Society The Liberal Arts University in the Age of AI and 'Activism' Ajay Skaria 5 minutes ago Spending some time on Ashoka University founder Sanjeev Bikhchandani's recent article may be helpful. First, it provides a concrete illustration of how generative AI can inhibit the capacity for critical thinking. Second, it helps us think about what we as teachers and citizens can do to guide those whose capacity for critical analysis has been weakened by AI. 'Ships in the Dark' a. 1927 painting by Paul Klee. Photo: Wikipedia. Real journalism holds power accountable Since 2015, The Wire has done just that. But we can continue only with your support. Contribute now Last summer, while in Kerala, I happened to read Benjamín Labatut's The Maniac. I was drawn to it because, two years earlier, a very dear friend had gifted me his previous book, When We Cease to Understand the World. Like that book, The Maniac is difficult to classify. It is fiction but draws so heavily on historical events that to call it fiction seems a bit of a stretch, though it would be even more of stretch to call it anything else. So let's resort to the copout of just calling it a book. Benjamin Labatut's 'The Maniac'. Though one might say it focuses primarily on the life and afterlife of John von Neumann, in the process The Maniac also traces the rise of artificial intelligence. Given the themes of his previous book, I have no doubt that Labatut is acutely aware of the social, political, and ecological implications of AI, but in The Maniac he focuses principally on its intellectual aspect; I shall be doing the same here (though, as we shall see, this may not really be possible). One of the book's most compelling chapters comes toward the end, when the world champion at Go, Lee Sedol, plays against an artificial intelligence program created by Google, AlphaGo, and loses. Go is an infinitely more complicated game than chess, and the kind of brute computational power that made possible the early unbeatable programs in chess would not have succeeded here. AlphaGo's creators built it instead on the more supple form of artificial intelligence, based on 'self-play and reinforcement learning, which meant that, in essence, it had taught itself how to play.' In The Maniac, Sedol describes his feeling after one of the moves: 'I thought AlphaGo was based on probability calculation and it was merely a machine. But when I saw this move it changed my mind. Surely AlphaGo is creative. This move made me think about Go in a new light. What does creativity mean in Go? It was not just a good, or great, or a powerful move. It was meaningful.' And then, in another game, Sedol makes a similar move, resulting in the only game he wrests from AlphaGo. Labatut writes: 'Facing each other, Lee and the computer had managed to stray beyond the limits of Go, casting a new and terrible beauty, a logic more powerful than reason that will send ripples far and wide.' Labatut's book, and that episode in particular, came to mind as an achingly poignant counterpoint while I read the response from one of Ashoka University's founders, Sanjeev Bikhchandani, to a former student from the University who wrote to him protesting the administration's silence on the hounding and eventual arrest on sedition charges of Professor Ali Khan Mahmudabad for his very reflective Facebook post. (The Supreme Court decision that released him on bail also has some astoundingly weak reasoning.) Bikhchandani vigorously defends the university's inaction over Mahmudabad's arrest and harassment, reproducing at length in the process an answer that Google AI generated for him when he asked it the question, 'Are all liberal arts universities activist in nature?' Bikhchandani says that he agrees with the AI's answer, and goes on to buttress it (to his mind) with additional points. I do not want to spend too much time on the specific arguments that Bikhchandani makes. The relatively valid ones are also very obvious ones: educational institutions cannot easily take strongly oppositional positions, especially against authoritarian regimes that do not follow or that systematically weaponise the rule of law; university administrations deal with regulators not only through public statements but also through institutional channels less in the public eye, and these administrations have only limited leeway in defying regulators; universities need money to function, and raising money for Ashoka is not easy. At a time when the attack on Ali Khan Mahmudabad is likely 'an excuse to corner and target Ashoka University,' I can certainly understand its administrators' and trustees' wanting to proceed cautiously. Two matters, however, vitiate these valid arguments. For one, there is all that his letter gets wrong, or glosses over. To briefly respond: as Priya Ramani notes, Bikhchandani's recollection that the college he studied in, St. Stephens, was free of activism during his time there is quite wrong. And the contrast he seems to be venturing between academic freedom and free speech is quite muddled, as would be clear to those more familiar with the relation and distinction, laid out very nicely in an essay by Adam Sitze. Besides, even his insistence that Mahmudabad was not engaged in academic freedom since he was engaged in speech outside academic venues does not quite hold up when we remember that Ashoka University's trustees and administration failed to defend Sabyasachi Das after the publication of his scholarly article on democratic backsliding in Indian elections. But even more worrisome is the second issue – the banality of Bikhchandani's arguments. This is a meta-issue, so to speak. The banal is worse than the wrong because the banal is also the abandonment of reflectiveness; it is the subversion of the ability to think critically about right and wrong because what is attenuated here is the ability to make meaningful distinctions about right and wrong. Indeed, if Labatut's book is an exploration of how AI might allow us – us, humans – to reach new artistic and intellectual and critical levels, Bikhchandani's article is a perfect example of the dulling of the critical – I deliberately do not say intellectual – faculties that will affect most people who allow their analytical capacities to be controlled by AI. Spending some more time on Bikhchandani's article may be helpful in two ways. First, it provides a concrete illustration of how generative AI can inhibit the capacity for critical thinking. Second, it helps us think about what we as teachers and citizens can do to guide those whose capacity for critical analysis has been weakened by AI. § Over the last three or so years, I have increasingly been incorporating into my courses a distinctive sort of assignment – one where students generate an answer using the AI involved in Large Language Models or LLMs (most stick to ChatGPT) to questions based on course material, and then produce a revised and meta-reflective version of the answer, both modifying it and explaining what they changed around and why. My students and I have found that when these models are fed social sciences-oriented questions (for now, let's just gloss those as questions where fidelity to facts is crucial) they get too many of their facts wrong. And when they are fed humanities-oriented questions (let's gloss those as questions where issues of meaning have to be probed), they are not so much wrong as banal, tending toward pabulum. Either way, what ChatGPT usually spits out is the kind of answer that in my classes would by itself be in the C range, or at most a B minus. In their engagement with the AI answer, differences between students also become clear. For the most reflective, the ChatGPT answer becomes an occasion to review their own presumptions more critically. What often results is something more brilliant and insightful than would likely have resulted if they had answered the question directly, without the ChatGPT detour. But the less reflective students usually find themselves concurring with ChatGPT. Even if they add quite a few factual corrections, they find it difficult to do more than add a small caveat or two to the humanistic questions of meaning that frame ChatGPT's arguments. And the students in the low C range end up offering etiolated versions of even the ChatGPT answer. How to help these weaker students develop a more thoughtful relation with generative AI is a matter that I continue to puzzle over. One thing that I have found somewhat helpful is asking students what groupthink might be embedded in the answers, and how and why might they want to take these answers apart. Illustration: Yutong Liu & Kingston School of Art/ Bikhchandani's reply to the student remains at the level of an LLM AI answer, as he himself effectively declares, and at times it sinks to the level of an etiolated version of such an answer; it is a good illustration of the kind of paper which in my undergraduate classes would get at best a C plus. In his case, of course, the problem starts with the question itself. From what I have seen, to get LLM AI models such as Google AI or ChatGPT to produce a half-decent answer to such a banal and generic question would be well-nigh impossible. One could, of course, come up with a more interesting answer to the question, but that would have to begin by reframing the question or probing its presumptions: asking more deeply what a liberal education is, asking what is glossed over in the term 'activist,' asking whether faculty and students and administration engage with 'activism' in necessarily different ways, and so on. But at present, at least, AI like Google's is incapable of that work. (To be clear, my remarks are only about the type of LLM AI Bikhchandani used: I have myself found, and others have, too, that when fed a delimited corpus and asked to generate answers on that basis, AI can be astonishingly good, and I can perhaps be persuaded that if I spent more time with feeding generative AI the right material, I might experience an AlphaGo moment.) Reframing Bikhchandani's question by critically parsing it would also be beginning to answer it. To carry out that task with the care it deserves would take longer than is possible in the compass of a short piece. But since Bikhchandani seems to have at least some curiosity about these matters, maybe one owes it to him to provide briefly the protocols that may help him critically move beyond the simple-minded embrace of Google AI pabulum. § So, in that educative spirit, here goes: No, 'liberal arts universities' are not 'necessarily activist' in nature – on this matter, Google AI is quite correct. Paradoxically, however, this is for several nested reasons which are about the different forms of action and activism at work in the concept of the university. 1) The relation between action and activism is a complex one, and we often invoke 'activism' in intellectually lazy ways. To put it very schematically for now: action that challenges what are taken to be prevalent social norms, whether of the right or left, is more likely to be classed as activism. 2) Conceptually, what distinguishes the modern university is that it is, for those who aspire to abide by its principle, a place focused on education as an autonomous end, rather than merely a place for technical training – that is, merely a means to transmit already formulated knowledge. I know, of course, that this aspiration has never been realised, and has always been undercut in many ways: from its very inception, there have been social exclusions that have shaped access to it for both faculty and students; since the 1980s, there has also been the neoliberal subordination of autonomy to the rhetoric of 'excellence.' But the aspirational dimension of the university cannot be easily extinguished, and this dimension is arguably especially important for the historically marginalised as they articulate the terms of the dignity they have been long denied. To treat education as an autonomous end means that we pursue both rational explanation and reflection as qualities in themselves. Such pursuit may lead to a departure from existing norms in a society or even within the university itself. This is why dissent is constitutive of the university as institution. And dissent even in speech means action. (Strikingly, Google AI recognises this more clearly than Bikhchandani. Its answer to him specifies that liberal arts education involves the 'development of critical thinking skills, not necessarily a commitment to activism.' Yes indeed, but this does not mean that activism is only 'a choice,' as Bikhchandani's sloppy regurgitation of Google AI's answer assumes.) 3) In other words, the modern university is founded on a distinction between thought/speech and action: the university is the place for thinking and speaking, and the world is the place for action. But that distinction is not an opposition. The terms bleed into each other: speech itself is an act, as is evident from the cases of Sabyasachi Das and Ali Khan Mahmudabad. Thought in this understanding has its meaning precisely because it is meant to inform and shape action, precisely because it assumed that action without thought is unacceptable The very commitment to action means that thinking must intervene in or at least speak up about action wherever the latter seems unthinking. Is this not activism? And should not university administrations defend this sort of 'activism' as the very principle of the university, even if on occasion, as when facing authoritarian regimes, administrations must choose their battles and defences strategically? Illustration: Hanna Barakat & Archival Images of AI + AIxDESIGN / / 4) So far I have addressed university education but not the adjective 'liberal.' In its application as an adjective to education, 'liberal' refers, as Wikipedia notes, to 'a system or course of education suitable for the cultivation of a free (Latin: liber) human being.' This sense of 'liberal' as an experience of being free – call it liberality – predates liberalism as an ideology which articulates a particular institutional order of freedom. And 'liberal education' has arguably retained more of that open-ended commitment to the idea of freedom, asking also what freedom is, than liberalism as ideology. It is precisely because of the destabilizing emphasis on 'free' that a liberal education tends by its very nature to be driven by a democratic spirit. But save in caricatural stoicisms, there is no such thing as a freedom of the mind that does not strive for a freedom in action. Would this not be another reason why a liberal education necessarily inclines toward not just action but activism? (This, though, is a very different matter from the claim that universities are 'necessarily activist,' as a shoddy – too quickly transitive – logic might assume.) 5) The focus here is not just on liberal education; it is on a liberal arts education. The phrase 'liberal arts' specifies a particular way of inhabiting the world – through critique. The crux of a liberal arts education as a concept is the combination of the sciences, centred as they are on explanation, expertise, and questions of 'what,' and the arts, centred as they are around reflection and questions of 'who.' Until just a few decades back, reflection was dominated by humanist reason, or a reason that made 'the human,' with all its constitutive exclusions, into the 'who.' Critical theory, increasingly prominent since the 1980s, represents an alternative tradition, one that is not humanist reason, but is not without reason. It emerges from the encounter, in friendship, of reasoning with the other and others it minoritises or places at its margins. 5) By at least the late 20th century, moreover, reflection had come include also the capacity to reflect critically on reason and try to practice a responsibility to what reason excludes – surely this could be one way of describing what is distinctive about critical theory. 6) While it makes sense empirically to distinguish between liberal universities and technical universities (those that teach only professional skills, and nothing of the humanities and social sciences), that distinction has no conceptual purchase. Even technical universities, when they treat technical education as an autonomous end, cannot avoid the liberal commitment involved in the undecidable and open-ended sense of freedom. 7) There is indeed a sense in which universities as institutions should not take activist positions, as Bikhchandani avers. But that sense becomes very complicated when we are attentive to it. The principal reason that universities might eschew activism is to keep open the institutional and conceptual space for students and faculty to engage in critical thought and the action – 'activism'? – from which thought is, in any meaningful sense, inseparable. This opening up of a space for students and faculty through institutional neutrality is an implication of the University of Chicago's Kalven report. To complicate things further, this emphasis on institutional neutrality does not always work, as critics have pointed out. For universities' own eschewal of activism remains tenuous: they must nourish in the wider societies of which they are part the capacity to engage in the critical thought that universities at their best embody. What happens when this nourishing of the capacity for critical thought is itself at odds with dominant or prevalent values in wider society? At that moment, should we say that a university pursuing its constitutive commitment to autonomous education has become activist? I know there is more to be said about each of these points, and also that there are more points to be made. But for now, consider this as offering some provocations for lifting Bikhchandani's C-plus level Google AI/ChatGPT-type piece to the kind of analysis one would expect from somebody who has had a liberal education. I do very much hope that Bikhchandani will take this opportunity to cultivate a deeper-than-AI understanding of liberal education, and more broadly of education as an autonomous activity: it would be wonderful to have trustees and founders who have such an understanding, whether in India or in the US, where they have repeatedly failed to understand what university education is about. Luckily, if Bikhchandani decides to go this route, there are many brilliant teachers at Ashoka University, including Ali Khan Mahmudabad, who can guide him. The gap between the AI answer to Bikhchandani's question and a more thoughtful reflection can also bring us back to what I have not been able to take up in this brief piece: the social and political dangers that AI poses. Where AI as an intellectual formation is dominant, I do not how we can avoid the dominance of the banal in social and political life. True, this banality may be most evident in the LLM type of AI, but it arguably occurs in more insidious ways in every form of AI as we know them today. And this social and political violence is quite apart from the tremendous environmental violence of AI. § There remains one other matter to be taken up: why have Bikhchandani's critical capacities – again, not at all to be confused with intellectual capacities – been so affected as to make him incapable of going beyond a Google AI-level understanding what a liberal arts education involves? My interest in this question does not centre on Bikhchandani individually or personally. For now at least, I am quite incurious about that. I am concerned more with the structural position he exemplifies. For Bikhchandani is not an exception. Silicon Valley and the worlds of finance, industry, and advertising teem with intelligent neoliberals who display a similar incomprehension about liberal education, who formulate banal questions about education (and many other subjects), and who do not even recognize the banality of their questions or the answers they generate. What accounts for this pervasive Dunning-Kruger effect? Put very schematically, it seems to me that a constitutive blindness is at work. Silicon Valley, as well as worlds such as those of finance or technology, deal primarily with issues that seem best addressed by a hypothetical imperative (that is to say, addressing issues that can be resolved in an 'if X, then Y' manner). Hypothetical imperatives, exemplified in instrumental reason, do not require persuasion or conversation. By contrast, as Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak famously notes, education involves the 'uncoercive rearrangement of desires.' I would add two observations to Spivak's remark: it is not just education, but also democratic sociality itself (including the capitalist sociality embodied in consumerism and advertising) that involves an uncoercive rearrangement of desires. Second, what is distinctive about modern education, especially at it gets involved in the question of reflection, is that here the uncoercive rearrangement of desires proceeds through critique, which is also to say through a division of the self, or a constant autocritique of desires. The act of loving another in their otherness is the other activity—the primary activity, really, of which education as an autonomous activity is but one privileged institutional form—in which the uncoercive rearrangement of desires proceeds through a division of the self. Precisely this insurmountable division of the self separates education, and love of the other in their otherness, from the uncoercive rearrangement of desires involved in consumerism, including most consumption of social media. The current crisis in the legitimacy of 'higher education' (the sphere in which education is most often regarded as an autonomous activity), and the increasing claim that universities are overrun by 'activists,' are surely related to a transformation in the relations between these three phenomena—the hypothetical imperative, liberal education as an other-oriented uncoercive rearrangement of desires, and consumerism as a self-oriented uncoercive rearrangement of desires. Illustration: Kathryn Conrad / / Until about the 1980s, it seems fair to say, the relation between the disciplines in the university and the hypothetical imperative was a cozy one. Thus, for much of the modern period, as Priya Satia notes, 'historians have not been critics but abettors of those in power'; the hypothetical imperative and liberal education seemed to condense in the same being—the one whom Frantz Fanon famously describes as 'the white man.' This was a time when it was possible to understand the hypothetical imperative as instrumental rationality, and liberal education as substantive or value rationality. This was a time when it was possible for many to hope that all would be well if only substantive rationality could control instrumental rationality, even as critics like Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno pointed to its impossibility. This was a time when it was commonplace to encounter the assertion that technology was not itself bad, and that what mattered was what 'man' did with it. By the 80s, however, the breakdown of that cozy relation was well under way. Two developments reinforced each other. On the one hand, neoliberalism emphasised the hypothetical imperative even more aggressively and had much less patience with the celebration of value rationality. What seemed much more attractive to this new order of the hypothetical imperative were the self-oriented forms of the uncoercive rearrangement of desires. Now, even for sympathetic neoliberals, liberal education can be affirmed only to the extent that it is a private pleasure, something carried out for one's private edification. Bikhchandani exemplifies this view in some of his remarks, as, for instance, in his yearning to be able to treat Ashoka as he would a private company. As for the neoconservative populisms that are becoming increasingly powerful, they perhaps recognize more clearly than the neoliberal position that it may be difficult to contain the university in this way, given its conceptual premises; this is why they seek to destroy the university as we know it. On the other hand, universities have seen the rise of various forms of critical theory, and the presence in much larger numbers of groups who had once been excluded from higher education. This has led to much less patience with value rationality, much more recognition of the fact that what was celebrated as value rationality was often the values of the dominant. At the same time, dissatisfaction with the world of the hypothetical imperative and its close twin, the self-oriented forms of the uncoercive rearrangement of desires, intensified. The university, and especially its students and faculty, increasingly emerged as the locus of the critique—a hesitant and often internally contradictory one, to be sure—of wider society to the extent that it was constituted by the hypothetical imperative and the self-centered uncoercive rearrangement of desires. It is this enormous gap that makes liberal education as a concept incomprehensible to somebody like Bikhchandani. At most, as I noted, his neoliberal perspective can celebrate liberal education as a private good – never as a public one. To treat it as a public good would be to acknowledge and affirm its potential to remake society. This neoliberalism – unlike liberalism – finds difficult to do. Indeed, Bikhchandani's incomprehension of the liberal university – his perception that the university has become a locus primarily of 'activism' – is more than anything a telling symptom of the attenuation of the critical tools with which to understand liberal education, or education as an autonomous activity. Ajay Skaria teaches in the Department of History and Institute for Global Studies at the University of Minnesota. This essay draws in part of some arguments expanded at greater length in his essay 'Gaza and the Unsettling Equality of Academic Freedom,' which is forthcoming in Critical Times (8:1). This essay first appeared on the Critical Times ' blog ' In the Midst.' The Wire is now on WhatsApp. Follow our channel for sharp analysis and opinions on the latest developments. Make a contribution to Independent Journalism Related News Ashoka University Can't Call Its Refusal to Stand Up to BJP's Bullying 'Institutional Neutrality' Founders of Ashoka Should Know that a University Can't be Equated With Hierarchies of a Corporate Office Is Ashoka University the Next Target After Professor Ali Khan? Who Gets to Think in India? Supreme Court's Bail Condition on Ashoka Professor Mahmudabad: Has Dissent Become Disorder? On Science and Changing Culture: A Conversation with Professor P. Balaram Ashoka Prof Arrested For 'Endangering Sovereignty' Over Post Criticising Jingoism, Sent to Custody Till May 20 'Inverted the Meaning, Invented an Issue': Ashoka Professor on Women's Panel's Reaction to Army Post The Curious Crusade of Renu Bhatia Against Ashoka Professor Mahmudabad View in Desktop Mode About Us Contact Us Support Us © Copyright. All Rights Reserved.

Manu Joseph: Why we must love the nation—other options are risky
Manu Joseph: Why we must love the nation—other options are risky

Mint

timea day ago

  • Mint

Manu Joseph: Why we must love the nation—other options are risky

A national secret is normally guarded by the government. But there is an Indian national secret that is held by India's people—probably thousands of them, or maybe millions. We can never be sure of the number. And the secret is that they may not be patriotic. It has to be a closely guarded secret because today every Indian is expected to be a patriot. The other option is simply not available. Whether you are in the government or opposed to it, everyone is expected to be patriotic. Even activists, 'rebels' with tattoos and long hair, posh avocado-eaters, rebellious teenagers and people who 'don't love anyone." Patriotism has become a foundational virtue. You can say you don't have some qualities, that you can't love, that you are greedy, that you do not think monogamy works. You can even say you are an atheist. But you cannot say you don't love the nation. Also Read: Manu Joseph: Where our freedom of speech came from and where it went Today, when people are critical of India, they add that they are critical because they so love the nation. Nobody has other reasons. A few days ago, Ali Khan Mahmudabad, an associate professor of political science at Ashoka University, was arrested. He had suggested that India's media briefings of Operation Sindoor, given by two women officers of the armed forces with Hindu and Muslim names, was important as 'optics" but needed to translate into ground reality for women and Muslims. In his defence, he stated that his views were 'entirely patriotic statements." Not long ago, intellectuals who challenged the state narrative were not expected to clarify that they were patriots. In fact, in the artistic and intellectual world, 'patriotism' is not a high ideal—rather, it is often seen as an emotion of the masses; even as one of the great dangers in the world. For instance, Rabindranath Tagore said, 'Patriotism cannot be our final spiritual shelter; my refuge is humanity." And George Bernard Shaw said, 'You'll never have a quiet world till you knock the patriotism out of the human race." And Bertrand Russell said: 'Patriotism is the willingness to kill and be killed for trivial reasons." Also Read: How India's middle-class came to be so patriotic Indian intellectuals or artists, it seems, do not say such things anymore. Some of them might be true patriots. Many of them may not be—just that they have to succumb to the expectation of being patriotic. Their public posture needs to be patriotic. I first noticed it when the writer Arundhati Roy faced sedition charges and imminent arrest in 2010, and she issued a brief statement saying, 'In the papers some have accused me of giving 'hate-speeches,' of wanting India to break up. On the contrary, what I say comes from love and pride." At the time, I felt it was uncharacteristic of her to use the words 'love' and 'pride' as emotions she felt for India. I did notice that for a writer of great clarity, she did keep the sentence a bit vague. Every major political party in India, including in Tamil Nadu, professes unconditional love for the nation. It is almost like time travel (and these days 'time travel' chiefly means a journey into the past, not the future), where a public moral is so sacred that everybody is expected to have it—and those who don't must keep quiet. When India wants our love, what does it mean, practically? We are among the most corrupt nations, our air is poisonous in many cities, our roads are congested, this is one of most unsafe places on earth for women, our quality of life is among the worst, and, according to the World Happiness Report, the average Indian is among the most unhappy people on earth. This is a country bereft of street joy—but we are expected to love it. Also Read: Manu Joseph: Just how 'innocent' are civilians during times of war? Yet, it makes sense. That is the nature of love, at least in most people. Like loveable people, a nation need not be filled with excellent qualities. A nation is not just pretty rivers and extraordinary bridges and skyscrapers and clean lanes. In fact, people struggle to define what a nation is—what unites all people. A nation is primarily a habit. A habit shared by diverse people. Nothing else binds a nation apart from this, and a love for this habit. So it is reasonable for a nation to expect its people to have that love as a fundamental attribute that cannot be questioned—and prudent for those who don't feel it to keep mum. Also, not loving a nation makes you a cultural orphan. There was a time, not long ago, when a few Indians—disenchanted with India or unable to respect it—assumed they were 'global people,' by which they almost never meant they belonged in Somalia, but that they belonged in the West. Also Read: Manu Joseph: We had more shame in the 1980s: Recall Bofors? But a lesson that this generation of India's upper class has learnt is that you primarily belong to your own people, because no one else cares enough. You need a home because everyone else has one. Without patriotism, a person is in the limbo of cultural orphanhood. Most people are patriots—including the new upper-middle-class and affluent Indians—because they do not belong outside India. Many are uncomfortable outside India. Everything about places outside India tends to make them suffer, probably after an initial one week of excitement. Even the chaos of India comforts them more than the tranquillity of a rich-world town. Even so, there are many people who value their emotions so much that they don't give them away easily. Or they value the words that come out of their mouth—the meaning of those words. People who want to attach a certain substance to what they say. And they are unable to say that they love India—partly because they are unable to say this aloud anymore. The author is a journalist, novelist, and the creator of the Netflix series, 'Decoupled'.

Dear Sanjeev Bikhchandani, supporting Prof Mahmudabad is a matter of morality, not activism
Dear Sanjeev Bikhchandani, supporting Prof Mahmudabad is a matter of morality, not activism

The Print

time2 days ago

  • The Print

Dear Sanjeev Bikhchandani, supporting Prof Mahmudabad is a matter of morality, not activism

Recently, I read your response to an alumnus of Ashoka University published in ThePrint. It is one thing to evade some issues for practical reasons and strategic concerns, but making that into a position paper, setting a certain precedent is a very different matter altogether. Hence, I feel there is something to be discussed here. My first memory of you is when you were addressing the first-year assembly at your alma mater and my workplace, St. Stephen's College, almost one-and-a-half decades ago. I have heard of and seen your support to the college, while also been a beneficiary of your positive responses to communications as a member of the college faculty. Let us look at the immediate concern: Ashoka professor Ali Khan Mahmudabad put up a Facebook post against terrorism of all kinds. Was it polarising and hateful? Did it attack the Indian Armed Forces at a time when a war between India and Pakistan was potentially looming large? I couldn't find anything against institutional interests, constitutional values or human rights in his post. Had you – the Ashoka administration – found anything problematic, your distancing yourself from his post would have been quite understandable. I couldn't find proof of that in your letter to the alumnus. Did Mahmudabad's post end up 'offending a whole bunch of people'? It must have, but then critical thinking (that one defining characteristic of liberal universities, as per the Google AI response in your letter) doesn't allow us to join the bandwagon of the feelings of a 'whole lot of people'. Does it? Some unanswered questions You call the faculty, students, alumni, and workers, including the founders, the 'Ashoka community'. One member of that community is remanded. Whatever the issue is, don't you have the responsibility to make sure he or she gets legal support, and work for the sustenance of an ambience in which his/her rights are protected? Wouldn't that be a position of institutional morality? Surely, the university shouldn't meddle with the legal processes. But providing legal support doesn't mean you support the views of the faculty or the student concerned. It only means you are trying to stand together as a community. The atmosphere of fear, which makes us avoidants in attending to certain duties of the community, will eventually make us shrink both individually and collectively. Isn't that concerning? I felt you avoided answering these specific questions by invoking larger, abstract questions of activism in a liberal university. Student collectives in universities have behaved in differently in three phases: when aristocratic young people were sent to medieval universities, they ganged up, created trouble, and ended up fighting with the local people – the infamous 'town and gown' quarrels that are associated with European universities in the Middle Ages. But the religious scholarship took a scientific turn through conflicts in the 17th century. Later, in the early 20th century, students supported the ruling establishment, famously in defeating Britain's 1926 General Strike and and in siding with Hitler in Germany. The anti-establishment common sense of universities is a thing of the '60s: female, coloured, lower-class, and minority students entering the previously guarded space of higher education en masse had a major role to play in it. They opposed capitalism where capitalism ruled, resisted communism in Eastern Europe where communism was in power, delegitimised the Cold War world order, brought out the limitations of socialist rhetoric of upper caste-dominant countries like India and formulated a new set of values for political rhetoric and academic inquiry. Essentialising liberal universities as activist in nature is not historically tenable. Universities have also never worked as per the intentions of their founders: the British government started colleges to produce clerks but the institutions became hotbeds of anti-colonial movements; Indira Gandhi's biggest academic investment, JNU, became a severe headache for her in a matter of six years. This is no surprise given the world does transform in ways we do not anticipate and universities are powerful ingredients and products of that process. In building a university, the community accumulates a culture beyond the topical and the immediate. But through all these phases, universities have been seen as critical habitats of ideation –spaces that gathered, stored, and disseminated those ideas – and produced new ideas and frames in the process. Both under monarchy and democracy, universities have come up with conversations, discussions and devices that caused paradigm shifts in the way we conduct our lives because there was a space in which people were able to actualise themselves. So, every university has had a need to establish communities that allow individuals to be ethically themselves and confident in their academic journey through life. Universities don't compulsorily have to be liberal – they could be neo-liberal or even conservative. But what it can't do is to say it's not a community. Creating a sense of belonging – not the university belonging to us but we belonging to the university – is central, would you not agree? Also read: There's a gap between what Ali Khan Mahmudabad said and what he's accused of—basic literacy Public and private institutions Ashoka University is a private university, and there is a school of thought that universities are best organised only in the public sphere. I have a different point of view. Given the huge leaps in technology and the very redefinitions of what it is to be human, a number of innovations are best done in private. For example, the Centre for Writing and Communication of Ashoka University is an effective and interesting innovation. Given the centre's structure and the numbers they have to deal with, a public university cannot do so and integrate new generational wisdom so easily. The idea of demonetising public universities to support private ones is not just dangerous but also completely impractical: Ashoka, given its financial requirements, cannot replace public universities. While one needs to be highly critical of the cynical heedlessness that public university leaders sitting in the executive and academic councils have been showing, it cannot be blamed on private entrepreneurs. That is another matter altogether. Without that, public and private universities can co-exist, compete, and even collaborate. A significant population of India has seen their financial condition improve in the last 20-25 years and private universities are one way to access that wealth. Academic orientation can function as a tributary in the field of art, nation-building, and knowledge production. Universities are spaces where people not only get degrees but acquire skills, develop perspectives, and learn to collectivise. While your initiative to start Ashoka University is appreciable, your translation of the current problem is potentially debilitating to the very possibilities a university promises. Lastly, a disagreement: St. Stephen's College had a very strong legacy of student activism – from CF Andrews, who taught at the college, raising his voice against British rule, to the women-led movements of the 2010s for equality and constitutional rights, especially the anti-CAA protests. You studied in a publicly funded college. You had enough sense of belongingness to come back and continue your engagement with the community. It is a function of its institutional value that prompts such an act. Do Indian private universities want such a possibility, of being a space of tomorrow, in another 20-30 years, seems to be the question that lingers on in this whole episode. Warmly, Ashley The author teaches English at St. Stephen's College, Delhi University. He tweets @NPAshley2. Views are personal. (Edited by Aamaan Alam Khan)

DOWNLOAD THE APP

Get Started Now: Download the App

Ready to dive into the world of global news and events? Download our app today from your preferred app store and start exploring.
app-storeplay-store